Chapter 1
An
Introduction
to
Logic
§ 1.1 STATEMENTS, NEGATIONS, CONJUNCTIONS,
DISJUNCTIONS, AND TRUTH TABLES.
The theory of logic was developed by many different
mathematicians, its roots were laid by
Aristotle, but reached a rigorous level by the nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries through the work of Boole, Frege, Whitehead, Russell,
Gödel, DeMorgan, etc. It is the one of
the basic building blocks and a foundation of higher level mathematics and
gives the mathematician the power to communicate reasoned ideas and thoughts
succinctly, clearly, and in an organised manner.
Logic is a formal study to analyze the process of
arriving at conclusions based on a given set of premises. Statements are declaratives that are either true or false, but can
not be both true and false simultaneously. A simple statements (or prime
statement or atom) is a declarative that is either true or false, but not
both and cannot be decomposed into any shorter group of statements that would
still constitute a meaningful sentence.
Examples of statements are: “The box is blue.” “If you
go to the market, then I will go to the sea.”
Whereas, "go to the store!" is not a statement, but a
command. Indeed the first statement,
“the box is blue,” is a simple statement; whereas, the second statement, ”if
you go to the market, then I will go to the sea,” is not since it is composed
of a simple statement, “you go to the market,” the simple statement, “I will go
to the sea,” and is connected by the connective, “if ð , then à .”
An argument is a collection of statements
called premises followed by a conclusion. The premises are statements which are assumed true, whilst the conclusion is a statement that may or
may not follow from the given set of premises (more on this later). So stated
differently, the study of logic is a formal study to determine if we assume all
the premises to be true, does the necessarily follow from the premises?
When a
person states something to you, do you agree that it is correct? Or do you question it and attempt to
determine if it is true or not?
For
example, if one person says, "it is raining," it is quite easy to
check to see if it is true or not; yet, it is more difficult to check to see if
the following is true or not, "If you make a 'A' on the next test, then I
will give you $10.00." The
statements are obvious, but will the promise be fulfilled? We will attempt to answer that question by
the end of this section.
We must
first understand the construct of an argument, and it should be noted that it
can take on many different forms. Let us
begin our discussion with some basic definitions for compound statements and
connectives. Once we understand compound statements we can then consider
arguments.
For example, suppose we have the following: Khalil has a red corvette. The opposite of this statement is Khalil does
not have a red corvette. The logical
opposite of a statement is called its negation.
If "Khalil has a red corvette" is symbolised by a "K," then
the negation, "Khalil does not have a red corvette," is symbolised by
“Ø K.”[1]
There are other ways to symbolise not K; for example, ~ K, - K, K¢,`K, KC are all used in different contexts to
mean not K. We shall adopt as a
convention the symbol Ø K, but interspersed in the text and exercises shall
be the congruent symbols.
Also, two statements can be joined by a connective
called the conjunction,
"and." Bob is tall and Mary is
blonde. Let us symbolise the first
statement, "Bob is tall," as "B" and the second statement,
"Mary is blonde," as "M."
So, we have the statement B and M, which shall be symbolised as B Ù M.
Suppose, however, we had the following two statements
joined by the connective called the disjunction,
"or." Raul is a New Yorker or
Sonya is saddened at the loss of her aunt.
Let us symbolise the first statement, "Raul is a New Yorker,"
as "R," and the second, "Sonya is saddened at the loss of her
aunt," as "S." So, we have the statement R or S, which shall be
symbolised as R Ú S.
Now, let us consider the validity of compound
statements. A compound statement is a statement such that it
decomposes into simple statements and connectives. Thus, the shortest compound statement would
be of the form not X where X is a simple statement since one cannot have
connectives without statements or two simple statements without a
connective.
Let us begin with Khalil. Suppose he has a red corvette. So, the
statement, "Khalil has a red corvette," is, of course, true,;
whereas, the statement, "Khalil does not have a red corvette," is
false. Similarly, if he does not have a red corvette, the statement,
"Khalil has a red corvette," is, of course, false, whereas, the
statement, "Khalil does not have a red corvette," is true.
We can represent this in the following manner using a truth table (a table constructed by listing all possible combinations of
true and false for the two separate statements followed by the result of the
combination of the two statements by the connective):
Truth Table 1.1.1
K |
ØK |
T |
F |
F |
T |
So, a truth
table is simply a diagramme that lists all possible truth values for the
simple statements and then the corresponding truth values for a compound
statement.
Suppose Bob is tall, and further Mary is blonde. Then, is the statement, "Bob is tall
and Mary
is blonde," true? Of course.
However, suppose Bob is tall, but Mary is not blonde. Then is the statement, "Bob is tall and
Mary is blonde," true? No, because
the statement, "Mary is blonde," is false. Suppose Bob is not tall, but Mary is
blonde. The statement, "Bob is tall
and Mary is blonde," is also false for the same reason as before: one of
the two conditions was false. Last,
suppose Bob is not tall, while Mary is not blonde. The statement, "Bob is tall and Mary is
blonde," is false because both statements are false. We can represent this in the following manner
using a truth table:
Truth Table 1.1.2
B |
M |
B Ù M |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
Now, let
us consider Raul and Sonya. Suppose Raul
is a New Yorker and Sonya is saddened at the death of her aunt. Is the
statement, "Raul is a New Yorker or Sonya is saddened at the death of her
aunt," true? Of course, since both
are true. Consider the situation if Raul
is a New Yorker, but Sonya is not saddened at the death of her aunt. Is the
statement, "Raul is a New Yorker or Sonya is saddened at the death of her
aunt," true? Yes, because one of the two statements was true. Continuing,
consider the situation if Raul is not a New Yorker, but Sonya is saddened at
the death of her aunt. Is the statement, "Raul is a New Yorker or Sonya is
saddened at the death of her aunt," true? Yes, because one of the two
statements was true. Finally, consider the situation if Raul is a not New
Yorker, while Sonya is not saddened at the death of her aunt. Is the statement,
"Raul is a New Yorker or Sonya is saddened at the death of her aunt,"
true? No, for both conditions are false, therefore, the disjunction is false.
We can represent this in the following manner using a
truth table:
Truth Table 1.1.3
R |
S |
R Ú S |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
Normally, the first statement is symbolised by a p and
the second statement is symbolised by a q, and lower case letters are oft used;
but, as you can see, this is not important.
The important part is considering all the possible combinations of true
and false and then determining if the conjunction, disjunction, or negation is
true or false.
Now let us combine two statements with more than one
connective. For example consider the
statement, it is not the case that Paul is perfect or Michael is creative. When we use the phrase, it is not the case
that , we mean that we are negating the entire statement . Therefore,
letting P be “Paul is perfect” and letting M be “Michael is creative” we find
that Paul is perfect or Michael is creative is symbolised as P Ú M. To negate
this requires us to use parentheses, so the statement, “it is not the case that
Paul is perfect or Michael is creative,” is symbolised as Ø (P Ú M).
A rule to
establish order of operations is necessary at this stage of the discussion;
thus, note the following (it will be expanded later):
Highest precedence parentheses
not
or/and and/or (from left
to right only) Lowest precedence
Thus, we can represent “it is not the case that Paul
is perfect or Michael is creative,”
Ø (P Ú M), in the following manner using a truth table:
Truth Table 1.1.4
P |
M |
P Ú M |
Ø(P Ú M) |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
Note that the order of operation is illustrated by the
columns of the truth table. Therefore,
in the construction of a truth table we should follow the order of operations.
Now let us combine more than two statements with more
than one connective. For example
consider the statement, Paul is not perfect or Michael is creative and Lisa is
lonely. Letting P be “Paul is perfect,”
M be “Michael is creative,” and L be “Lisa is lonely,” we find that Paul is
perfect or Michael is creative and Lisa is lonely is symbolised as P Ú M Ù L.
Nonetheless, note that the order of operation requires the conjunction
and disjunction to be of the same precedence and we order from left to right.
Therefore, Paul is perfect or Michael is creative and Lisa is lonely is
symbolised as (P Ú M) Ù L.
Also, note that four rows for the truth table is not
sufficient. There are eight ways to
combine true and false in order to represent all the possibilities for the
truth of each simple statement
Truth Table 1.1.5
P |
M |
L |
P Ú M |
(P Ú M) Ù L |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
Note that
the statement did not properly use punctuation. The statement, Paul is not
perfect or Michael is creative and Lisa is lonely is properly punctuated as, “,
Paul is not perfect or Michael is creative, and Lisa is lonely.” We cannot allow for ambiguity, thus, if the
statement is not properly punctuated, we adopt the convention that punctuation
follows the order of precedence.
Let us consider a different statement, Paul is not
perfect, or Michael is creative and Lisa is lonely. Noting connectives,
punctuation, and letting P be “Paul is perfect,” M be “Michael is creative,”
and L be “Lisa is lonely,” we find that Paul is perfect, or Michael is creative
and Lisa is lonely is symbolised as P Ú (M Ù L).
The truth table is therefore:
Truth Table 1.1.6
P |
M |
L |
M Ù L |
P Ú (M Ù L) |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
Note the truth values obtained for the statement in
table 6 are different than in table 5.
Two statements are said to be equivalent (or synonymous, the same, or logically equivalent)
only in the instance where the final column of the compleat truth tables are
the same where the prime statements were assigned truth values in the exact
same order. Suppose the statement X is
equivalent to Y, we symbolise this as X º Y. Two statements are said to non- equivalent in the
instance where they are not equivalent (duh). Suppose the statement X is not
equivalent to Y, we symbolise this as X Y.
Finally two statements, X and Y, are said to be logical opposites in the instance where X º ØY (and Y º ØX).
As with
any convention, when we wish to symbolise not a particular property in symbol
form, we slash through the symbol to represent such a scenario.
Note, that the negation of the conjunction Ø (p Ù q) is
equivalent to the disjunction
Øp
Ú
Øq (it is left as an exercise to
verify). Also note, the parentheses are necessary, for the statement Ø (p Ù q) is not the same as Ø p
Ù
q (see truth tables 1.7 and 1.8)!
This is problematic for some people for they might erroneously think the
two are the same. For colloquial
statements in English, this can be a problem, but for proper statements in
logic it is not. Let us assign to the
symbol p the simple statement “it is pouring” and assign to the symbol q the
simple statement Natasha is quick. Now,
the statement, it is not pouring and Natasha is quick is Ø p Ù q;
whereas, the statement, it is not the case that it is pouring and Natasha is
quick is, Ø (p
Ù
q). Since Ø (p Ù q) is
equivalent to Øp
Ú
Øq, for many it would be clearer if
one simply said, “it is not pouring or Natasha is not quick.”
Truth Table 1.1.7
P |
Q |
P Ú Q |
Ø(P Ú Q) |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
Truth Table 1.1.8
P |
Q |
ØP |
ØP Ú Q |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
§ 1.1 EXERCISES.
1. Construct a compleat
truth table for the following statements, identify which statements are
logically equivalent, which statements are logical opposites, and which are
neither:
A. Øp Ù q B. p Ù ~q
C. p Ù ~q D. p Ù q
E. Øq Ú p F. Øp Ú q
G. p Ù ~p H. ~ (p Ú q)
I. ~ (p Ù q) J. p Ú Øp
2. Construct a compleat
truth table for the following statements:
A. p Ù q Ú p Ù r B. p Ù (q Ú p) Ù r
C. p Ù q Ú (p Ù r) D. (p Ù q) Ú (p Ù r)
E. Øp Ù q Ú p Ù r F. p Ù ~(q Ú p) Ù r
G. p Ù q Ú H. (p Ù Øq) Ú (p Ù r)
§ 1.2 CONDITIONAL
AND BICONDITIONAL STATEMENTS
Now, let us investigate the statement, "If you
make a 'A' on the next test, then I will give you $10.00."
Let us symbolise "if you make an 'A' on the next
test as, p, and the statement "I will give you $10.00," as q. So, we
have: if p, then q. This statement is
called the conditional, and is
symbolised by : p Þ q . It is also
symbolised by p ® q, q Ü p, p \ q, and q ¬ p. The
statement p is called the hypothesis
or antecedent and the statement q is
called the consequent or conclusion.
Now, on to
the argument. Suppose you make an 'A' on the next test and I give you
$10.00. Is the statement, "if you
make a 'A' on the next test, then I will give you $10.00," true? Yes,
because I kept my promise. However,
suppose you make an 'A' on the next test and I do not give you $10.00. Is the statement, "if you make a 'A' on
the next test, then I will give you $10.00," true? No, I have broken my
promise to you. Next, suppose you do not make an 'A' on the next test, but I do
give you $10.00. Is the statement,
"if you make a 'A' on the next test, then I will give you $10.00,"
true? Yes. You have not made the 'A,'
but out of the generosity of my heart, I still provide you with the
$10.00. Last, suppose you do not make an
'A' on the next test and I do not give you $10.00. Is the statement, "if you make a 'A' on
the next test, then I will give you $10.00," true? Yes. You have not made the 'A,' and I do not
provide you with the $10.00. The promise still held, because you did not fulfil
your part of the bargain. So, notice if
the first part of the conditional is false, it does not matter what happens in
the second part- the conditional (the promise) is true. The point of this
discussion is that burden of following through on the promise (thus, the
conditional) is on me (q; the consequent).
There is no such burden on you (p; the antecedent) since no promise was
made by you. We can represent this in the following manner using a truth table:
Truth Table 1.2.1
p |
q |
p Þ q |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
The last
two rows of the truth table illustrate a condition called the condition of vacuous truth for a conditional. It illustrates that when the antecedent is
false the conditional is always true. For example, “if donkeys fly, [fill in
the blank],” for donkeys do not fly
so you can say whatever you wish and the conditional is true no matter what is
filled in for the blank. Note that this
is the case since the conditional cannot be shown to be false when the
antecedent is false. Note also that the
first and third rows of the truth table illustrate that when the consequent is
true the conditional is always true.
Hence, of prime importance is the second row. Focus on that row for it is the row where the
conditional is false. There should never
be a case where one argues with a true antecedent implying a false consequent
(though the world is rife with examples of just such argument forms).
Recall truth table 1.1.8. Compare
truth table 1.1.8 and 1.2.1. Note that
these demonstrate that p Þ q º Øp Ú q.
There are many variations of the wording for the conditional. You must learn these so that you become adept
at reading and listening to mathematics.
The conditional P Þ Q , P ® Q , Q Ü P , or Q ¬ P translates
to:
(1) If P, then Q.
(2) Q, if P
(3) P hence Q
(4) Q whence P
(5) P is a sufficient condition for Q
(6) Q is a necessary condition for P
(7) P only if Q
(8) If not Q, then not P
(9) P implies Q
(10) Not P, or Q
(11) Q whenever P.
So, consider the
conditional, “if Alexis is running, then Blake is driving;” stated as a
conditional version (1) from above would be (in alternate wording from above):
(2) Blake drives
if Alexis runs.
(3) Alexis runs
hence Blake drives.
(4) Blake runs
whence Alexis drives.
(5) Alexis to be
running is a sufficient condition for Blake to be driving.
(6) It is
necessary that Blake drive for Alexis to be running.
(7) Alexis runs,
only if Blake drives.
(8) If Blake
doesn’t drive, then Alexis does not run.
(9) Alexis
driving implies Blake runs.
(10) Alexis
doesn’t run or Blake is driving.
(11) Blake drives
whenever Alexis runs.
When at least one of the prime statements
in the conditional represents a group, then the translation can be slightly
different. The conditional P Þ Q translates to:
(12) All Ps are Qs.
(13) No Ps are not Qs.
(14) All of the Ps have the property of Q.
(15) None of the Ps are not Qs.
For example,
consider the conditional, “if that thing is a bird, then it is an animal;”
would be:
(12) All birds
are animals.
(13) No birds are
not animals.
(14) All of the
birds have the property of being animals.
(15) None of the
birds are not animals.
Thus, there are at least fifteen different
ways to state a conditional in idiomatic English. The student should learn the
different ways to state the conditional; understand the uses (when using plural
versus singular concepts); and, be comfortable translating from English to
symbols, symbols to English, symbol form to alternate symbol form, and from
English form to synonymous English form.
The biconditional
is a compound of two conditionals, if p, then q and if q, then p. Take, for
example, p: I am happy, and q: you are gardening. We would for the biconditional have, "if
I am happy, then you are gardening," AND, "if you are gardening, then
I am happy." This is very
cumbersome, so we have an easier way to state the biconditional: "I am
happy if and only if you are
gardening." One can see that by
checking each individual conditional the p
Þ q is false only when p is true, and q is false,
and the q Þ p is false
only when q is true and p is false, then combining the two conditionals with a
conjunction yields the following:
Truth Table 1.2.2
p |
q |
p Þ q |
q Þ p |
(p Þ q) Ù (q Þ p) |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
Which can be
simplified to:
Truth Table 1.2.3
p |
q |
p Û q |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
by replacing (p Þ q) Ù (q Þ p) with the more parsimonious symbol p Û q.
The
biconditional P Û Q or P « Q translates
to:
(1) P if and only if Q.
(2) P iff Q (this is just a shorthand for version 1).
(3) P is necessary and sufficient for Q.
(4) P and Q are logically equivalent.
(5) If P then Q and if Q then P.
Condition (4)
establishes that two statements, P and Q, are logically equivalent in the
instance where P Û Q is true for note the only time when P Û Q is true is when both P and Q are true or when both
P and Q are false.
Since we have two more symbols we must add them to our order of
precedence
Highest precedence parentheses ( )
not ~, Ø, or ___
and/or (from left to
right) Ù Ú
conditional
Þ ®
biconditional Û « Lowest precedence
Note when two
symbols of equal precedence are connecting, then precedence is from left to
right (e.g.: P Þ Q Þ R means (P Þ Q) Þ R); but non-equal precedence does not follow left to right but by order of precedence (e.g.: P Þ Q Ù R means P Þ (Q Ù R) and P Ù Q Þ R means (P Ù Q) Þ R).
Various types of statements are of interest to mathematicians. A
compound statement is a tautology
when the compound statement is true for every true-false combination. A
statement is a fallacy when the
statement is true for at least one true-false combination and is false for at
least one true-false combination. A contradiction is a compound statement
that is false for every true-false combination for the prime statements.
We are interested in discerning what
statement forms are tautologies, fallacies, or contradictions so that when we
begin investigating argument forms, we can use tautologies or contradictions
and avoid fallacies. A tautological argument is that which we
attempt to construct when we prove an assertion.
Finally there is one other type of disjunction, the exclusive disjunction, which is
symbolised as P Q. We reference this because there are times in
mathematics when we do not want to have the possibility of both conditions
being satisfied but wish to have one or the other exclusively satisfied.
P or Q, but not both.
P exclusive or Q.
P exor Q.
Truth Table 1.2.4
p |
q |
p |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
Note that P Q is the logical
opposite of P Û Q.
§ 1.2 EXERCISES.
1. Construct a compleat
truth table for the following statements, identify which statements are
logically equivalent, and which statements are logical opposites:
A. Øp Ù q B. p Þ q
C. Øp ® Øq D. p Ü q
E. p Ù ~q F. p Û Øq
G. p Ù q H. Øq Ú p
I. Øp Ú q J. Øp ® q
K. Øq ® Øp L. q ® p
M. Øq Þ q N. p Ù ~p
O. p Þ p P. ~ (p Ú q)
Q. ~ (p Ù q) R. p ® p
2. Construct a compleat
truth table for the following statements:
A. (p Ù Øq) Ú (p Ù r) B. p Þ q Ú p Ù r
C. p Ù (q ® p) Ù r D. p ® q Ú (p Ù r)
E. (p Ù q) Þ (p Ù r) F. (p Ù q) Þ p
G. (p Ù q) Þ q H. (p Ú q) Þ p
I. (p Ú q) Þ q J. p Þ p Ú q
K. q Þ p Ú q L. q Þ p Ú q Ú r
3. Let p be
"it is foggy" and q be "it is cold."
Translate each of
the following into symbolic logic.
A. It is foggy or
it is cold.
B. It is not
foggy and it is not cold.
C. If it is
foggy, then it is warm or hot.
D. The day being
foggy is a necessary and sufficient condition for it to be cold.
E. It is false
that it is both cold and foggy.
4. Write the
negation of the following in standard colloquial written English:
A. Either we will
buy ice cream or we will rent a movie.
B. Cynthia is
charming and Paul is well-mannered.
C. It is false
that Rameses is happy and Colette is sad.
D. Ashton is not
wealthy.
5. Translate the
following into symbolic form (do not forget to define symbols representing
prime statements):
A. If this is Tuesday, we must be in Belgium.
B. It is a bird, if it is an eagle.
C. All people have heads.
D. She has no cash or she has a charge plate.
E. p2 ¹ 25, p =
5, or p = -5.
F. | y + 6 | ¹ 8 and y = 2 or y = -14.
G. If x + 3 = 5, then x = 1 or x = 2.
H. If z = 1 and z = 5, then z2 + 2z +
1 = 0.
I. It is snowing implies it is below 32° F.
J. It is not snowing or it is below 32° F.
K. It is necessary that x < 2 for x + 1 <
3.
L. If the Mets win every game left in the
season, then they will win the N. L. East.
M. Tom always buys an Oldsmobile.
N. Sarah buys a Toy when she is in New York.
O. No chicken are teetotalers.
P. I love New York.
Q. Nobody is alone who cares for a pet.
R. Watering grass is sufficient for grass to
grow.
S. If the butler did it, then the maid
didn’t. The butler or the maid did
it. If the maid did it, then the butler
did it.
T. If math was interesting, then I would earn an
‘A.” Math isn’t interesting. Thus, I am
not earning an “A.”
U. No alterations, redecorating, tacks, or nails
shall be made in the building, unless written permission is obtained.
V. Babies are illogical. Nobody is despised who can manage a
crocodile. Illogical people are
despised.
W. If the population increases rapidly and
production remains constant, then prices rise.
If prices rise then the government will control prices. I am rich then I do not care about increases
in prices. It is not true that I am not
rich. Either the government does not control prices or I do not care about
increases in prices. Therefore, it is not the case that the population
increases rapidly and production remains constant.
X. Dean praises me only if I can be proud of
myself. Either I do well in classes or I
cannot be proud of myself. If I do my
best in sports, then I cannot be proud of myself. Therefore, if Dean praises me, then I do my
best in sports.
Y. If Winston or Halbert wins then Luke and
Susan cry. Susan does not cry. Thus, Halbert does not win.
Z. If I enroll in the course and study hard,
then I will earn acceptable grades. If I make satisfactory grades, then I am
content. I am not content. Hence, either
I did not enroll in this course or I did not study hard.
AA. If he goes to the party, he does not fail
to brush his hair. To look fascinated
is necessary to be tidy. If he is a
sushi eater, then he has no self-command.
If he brushes his hair, he looks fascinated. He wears white gloves only
if he goes to the party. Having no
self-command is sufficient to make one look untidy. Therefore, sushi eaters do not wear white
gloves.
BB. No ducks waltz. No officer ever declined
to waltz. All my poultry are ducks. Thus, None of my poultry are officers.
CC. Everyone who is sane can do logic. None of your sons can do logic. No lunatics
are fit to serve on the jury. Therefore,
if he is your son, then he is not on the jury.
DD. The sum of an irrational number and a
rational number is an irrational number.
EE. The product of two negative numbers is a
positive number.
FF. The square root of a positive number is a
positive number.
GG. only if
.
HH. If
then
.
II. The square of a negative number is a positive
number.
JJ (dyn-o-mite!).
a3 = 8, b = 3, and c = 1.
KK. 7 < 3 and
5 > 4, or 2 = 1.
LL. a2
+ b2
= g2
whence a = 3, b = 4, and g = 5.
MM. All of the
dated letters in this room are written on blue paper. None of them are in black
ink, except those that are written in the third person. I have not filed any of
those I have not read. None of those that are written on one sheet are undated.
All of those that are not crossed out are written in black ink. All of those
that are written by Mr. Brown begin with “Dear Sir.” All of those that are
written on blue paper are filed. None of those that are written on more than
one sheet are crossed out. None of those
that begin with “Dear Sir” are written in the third person. Hence, I cannot
read any of Mr. Brown’s letters.
6. Translate the
following into symbolic form (do not forget to define symbols representing
prime statements) and supply a valid conclusion:
A. No kitten that loves fish is uneducable. No kitten without a tail will play with a
gorilla. Kittens with whiskers always
love fish. No educable kitten has green
eyes. No kittens have tails unless they have whiskers.
B. Promise-breakers are untrustworthy. Alcohol
drinkers are very verbose. A person who keeps a promise is honest. No
teetotalers are pawnbrokers. One can trust a very loquacious person.
C. All the dated letters in this room are
written on embossed paper. None of them
are in black ink, except those that are written in the third person. I have not filed any of them that I can
read. None of them that are written on
one sheet are undated. All of them that
are not crossed are in black ink. All of
them written by Thomas Brown, Esq. Begin with “Dear Sir.” All of them written
on embossed paper are filed. None of
them written on more than one sheet are crossed. None of them that begin with
“Dear Sir” are written in the third person.
§ 1.3 THE LAWS
OF LOGIC
In mathematics oft times there are
concepts that are intuitive or practical that are allowed such that there is
general agreement to allow for the claim that such may be assumed. These
claims are called axioms or postulates and are the basic ideas that
underlie a particular area of mathematics.
Further, there is oft a need to introduce
other concepts, notation, symbols, etc.
These are called definitions
for they describe a class of objects, a symbol, or other such
fundamentals. The purpose of a
definition is to avoid ambiguity, so that clarity, objectivity, and rigor is
maintained. Many definitions are no
doubt familiar to you, the reader, for example the definition of the symbol “=,
” or the definition of a natural number.
However, the definition of a concept may differ depending on context,
author, subject, class, etc. Some
authors define the natural numbers to be the collection of numbers 0, 1, 2, 3,
4, 5, ¼; whilst others define the natural numbers to be the
collection of numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ¼ . Now clearly
these are not logically the same collections[2]
but it doesn’t really matter in the long run.[3] What does matter is that an author, an
instructor, etc. must define the
meaning of the term natural numbers before proceeding with a discussion of the
natural numbers or use of them.
Some definitions
will be completely new to you, the student, and thus will have to be learnt
without prior exposure. For example,
suppose the author defines a “brent” to be any rational number such that when
expressed in reduced fraction form the denominator is 3. So, a student can easily see that .5 is not
a brent, .3 is not a brent, but is a brent, 1 is not a brent, p is not a brent, .67 is not a brent, but
is a brent.
Furthermore, the definition must
completely specify the concept and cannot allow for something to be both the
concept and not the concept for that would be self-contradictory; hence,
useless (and see the law of double negation below).
We want a
definition to be of use and not self-contradictory; for example, in everyday life the concept of
tall is not well defined since it is ambiguous, contextual, and
subjective.
Axiom 1:
All prime
statements P, Q, R, etc. are statements.
If P is a
statement, then Ø P is a statement.
If P and Q are
statements, then P Ú Q is a statement.
If P and Q are
statements, then P Ù Q is a statement.
If P and Q are
statements, then P Þ Q is a statement.
If P and Q are
statements, then P Û Q is a statement.
Given the
previous, then we can deduce that there are tautological statements that are of
use to us.
Idempotent Law (1) P Ú P º P
Idempotent Law (2) P Ù P º P
Truth Table 1.3.1
P |
P Ú P |
T |
T |
F |
F |
Truth Table 1.3.2
P |
P Ù P |
T |
T |
F |
F |
Law of Double Negation Ø (Ø P) P [ same as
Ø (Ø P) Û P ]
Truth Table 1.3.2
P |
ØP |
Ø(Ø P) |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
Law of the Excluded Middle (1) P Ú ØP is always
true[4]
Law of the Excluded Middle (2) P Ù ØP is always
false [5]
(Law of Contradiction)
Please note that
these laws are central to basic (dichotomous) logic. Therefore, we note the following truth tables
as support for the assertion.
Truth Table 1.3.3
P |
Ø P |
P Ú ØP |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
Truth Table 1.3.4
P |
Ø P |
P Ù ØP |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
Material Implication P
Þ Q Ø P Ú Q
(The Or Form of the Implication)
(note: when
changing from implication to or form reference or form; when changing from or
form to implication reference implication form; or, just reference material
implication)
Truth Table 1.3.5
P |
Q |
P Þ Q |
ØP |
Ø P Ú Q |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
Table 1.3.5 illustrates the use of one truth table to demonstrate the
logical equivalence of two statements.
It is most useful when typing since the letter denoting true or false
for the claim can be highlighted using the bold function in a word processing
function of a computer. However, when writing a justification of the logical
equivalence of two statements it is best to do two separate tables.
Contrapositive Form of the Implication P
Þ Q Ø Q Þ Ø P
(Transposition)
Truth Table 1.3.6
P |
Q |
P Þ Q |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
Truth Table 1.3.7
P |
Q |
ØQ |
ØP |
ØQ Þ ØP |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
De Morgan’s Law (1) Ø P Ú ØQ Ø (P Ù Q)
De Morgan’s Law (2) Ø P Ù ØQ Ø (P Ú Q)
Truth Tables (exercises 1A and 1B)
Exportation P Ù R Þ Q (P Þ (R Þ Q))
(Direct Proof Law)
Truth Table (exercise 1C)
Indirect Proof Law
P Ù ØQ Þ a false
statement P Þ Q must be true
Truth Table (exercise 1D)
The meaning of
the indirect proof law is that one can prove P Þ Q is true by
showing if one assumes P and not Q
you get a false statement (a contradiction, we will not later). This law is easier to understand in practice
than symbolically.
Commutative Law
of “or” (1) P Ú Q Q Ú P
Commutative Law
of “and” (2) P Ù Q Q Ù P
Truth Tables (exercises 1E and 1F)
Associative Law
of “or” (1) P Ú (Q Ú R) (P Ú Q) Ú R
P Ú Q Ú R
Associative Law
of “and” (2) P Ù (Q Ù R) (P Ù Q) Ù R
P Ù Q Ù R
Truth Tables (exercises 1G and 1H)
Distributive Law of “and over or” (1) P Ù (Q Ú R) (P Ù Q) Ú (P Ù R)
Distributive Law of “or over and” (2) P Ú (Q Ù R) (P Ú Q) Ù (P Ú R)
Truth Tables (exercises 1I and 1J)
Law of Disjunctive Addition (Law of
Addition) P Þ P Ú Q
Truth Table 1.3.8
P |
Q |
P Ú Q |
P Þ P Ú Q |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
Law of Conjunctive Simplification (Law of
Simplification) P Ù Q Þ P
Truth Table 1.3.9
P |
Q |
P Ù Q |
P Ù Q Þ P |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
Of course, P Ù Q also implies Q, but this is not stated as a law
since one can argue that P Ù Q is logically equivalent to Q Ù P (by the commutative law); then applying the law of
simplification, it is the case that we have Q.
Also, note that oft times students
confuse the law of addition and the law of simplification. You must remember
that “or does not reduce - - it adds” whilst “and reduces it never adds.” If these are confused, then many “proofs”
that students produce are not worth the paper on which the “proofs” were
written.
Modus Ponens [(P
Þ Q) Ù P ] Þ Q
Truth Table (exercise 1K)
Modus Tollens [(P
Þ Q) Ù ØQ] Þ ØP
Truth Table (exercise 1L)
Disjunctive Syllogism [(P
Ú Q) Ù ØQ] Þ P
Truth Table (exercise 1M)
Hypothetical Syllogism [
(P Þ Q) Ù (Q Þ R)] Þ [P Þ R ]
(Transitivity)
Truth Table (exercise 1N)
Assume the hypothesis of the conclusion (P Þ (R Þ Q)) Þ (P Ù R) Þ Q
Truth Table (exercise 1O)
Constructive Dilemma [
(P Þ Q) Ù (R Þ S) Ù (P Ú R)] Þ [Q Ú S ]
Truth Table (exercise 1P)
Destructive Dilemma [
(P Þ Q) Ù (R Þ S) Ù (ØQ Ú ØS)] Þ [ØP Ú ØR]
Truth Table (exercise 1Q)
Whilst most texts note the laws of logic
and the rules of inference, it is not sufficient in my opinion; stating the
laws is all well and good but it is also helpful to note the fallacies to
avoid. Therefore, we shall also discuss
some fallacies of logic and rhetoric.
One of the most pernicious mistakes
students make is asserting the conclusion.
They are often taught this is a valid method of reasoning in high school
(by teachers who have no business
teaching, I might add) or induce that it is a reasoning pattern that is valid
from typical high school mathematics problems such as:
(1) Let the
universe be the real numbers. Consider the equation x2 + x - 5 =
0. Solve for x. Solution:
x = -3 or x = 2.
(2) Let the
universe be the real numbers. Reduce (16)(64)-1. Solution: .25.
Note that the assumption was made in the
statement of the first problem that the equality held. So, a student can by
trial and error reach the solution without knowledge of factoring, completion
of the square, or the quadratic equation. Note that the assumption was made in
the statement of the second problem that it could be reduced. Then a
non-mathematical solution would be to plug it into a calculator or reduce it
incorrectly. So, a student can reach the solution without knowledge of
factorisation and proper methods of cancellation.
However, assuming a conclusion and then
“filling in the details” is fraught with problems. Let us illustrate this with
the second problem noted above.
Consider four students A, B, C, and D.
Student A
considers the problem. Let the universe be the real numbers. Reduce (16)(64)-1.
He reaches for
his TI - 89 and punches 16, 64, yx, -1, and =. He sees .25 in the screen and writes down the
answer. What does he really know?
Student B
considers the problem. Let the universe be the real numbers. Reduce (16)(64)-1.
She reaches for
her Casio 4 and punches 16, 64, ¸, and =. She
sees .25 in the screen and writes down the answer. What does she really know?
Student C
considers the problem. Let the universe be the real numbers. Reduce (16)(64)-1.
He writes 16 .
64-1 = =
=
. We know he has
incorrectly applied the real variable law of cancellation.
Student D
considers the problem. Let the universe be the real numbers. Reduce (16)(64)-1.
He writes 16 .
64-1 = =
=
=
=
. We know he has correctly applied real
variable cancellation and knows what
he is doing.
When asserting a conclusion to a claim,
one is already done. Let us illustrate
this point by noting the following.
Suppose all boys are rugged. All
rugged things are tall. Suppose from this we wish to say, “all boys are
two-footed.”
Now, to begin let us assume all boys are two-footed.
So? What’s our point? We are already at the conclusion. Did this mean that the first two sentences in
the claim necessarily imply the conclusion? Of course not, we are making one of
the oldest mistakes in reasoning: asserting the conclusion. Perhaps (I believe
it is the case) this was not the best example; but it shows how asserting the
conclusion really is quite the mistake.
The Fallacy of Asserting the Conclusion [(P
Þ Q) Ù Q] Þ P
( assuming the conclusion) (fallacy of the converse)
Truth Table 1.3.10
P |
Q |
P Þ Q |
(P Þ Q) Ù Q |
[(P Þ Q) Ù Q] Þ P |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
It is actually
the case that necessarily!
The Fallacy of Asserting the Premise (P
Þ Q) Þ P
( assuming the hypothesis of an implication must
always be true)
Truth Table 1.3.11
P |
Q |
P Þ Q |
(P Þ Q) Þ P |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
It is actually the case that necessarily! Also note that since there are two false entries
in the last column of the truth table versus one false entry in the last column
of truth table 1.3.10 does not make the fallacy of asserting the conclusion
“better” than the fallacy of asserting the premise. A fallacy is a fallacy - - no more, no less.
Arguing on the basis of a fallacy, fallacious reasoning, over-generalising,
etc. are all wrong and should be avoided.
The Fallacy of Denial of the Hypothesis of a
Conditional [(P Þ Q) Ù ØP] Þ ØQ
(fallacy of the inverse)
Truth Table 1.3.12
P |
Q |
P Þ Q |
ØP |
(P Þ Q) Ù ØP |
ØQ |
[(P Þ Q) Ù ØP]Þ ØQ |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
It is actually
the case that necessarily!
The Fallacy of Reduction of Or P Ú Q Þ P
(incorrectly
reversing the law of addition)
Truth Table (exercise 2A)
The Fallacy of Construction of And P
Þ P Ù Q
(incorrectly
reversing the law of simplification)
Truth Table (exercise 2B)
There are MANY
more fallacies we could list; but these are the most common I have come across
in grading proofs. Avoid them!
§ 1.3 EXERCISES.
1. Construct a compleat
truth table for the following laws. Note
why such is a law.
A. De Morgan Law (1)
B. De Morgan Law (2)
C. Exportation
D. Indirect Proof Law
E. Commutative Law of
“or” (1)
F. Commutative Law of
“and” (2)
G. Associative Law of
“or” (1)
H. Associative Law of
“and” (2)
I. Distributive Law of “and over or” (1)
J. Distributive Law of “or over and” (2)
K. Modus Ponens
L. Modus Tollens
M. Disjunctive Syllogism
N. Hypothetical Syllogism
O. Assume the
hypothesis of the conclusion
P. Constructive Dilemma
Q. Destructive Dilemma
2. Construct a compleat
truth table for the following fallacies.
Note why such is a fallacy.
A. The Fallacy of Reduction of Or
B. The Fallacy of Construction of And
C. (P Þ Q) º (Q Þ P)
D. (P Þ Q) º (ØP Þ ØQ)
§ 1.4 ARGUMENTS,
ARGUMENT FORMS, PROOFS, AND
COUNTEREXAMPLES.
Suppose we have a set of propositions and
we wish to determine if there is some statement that can be drawn from the
propositions. An argument may be defined as any group of propositions of which one
is claimed to follow from the others, which are regarded as supplying evidence
for the truth of that one. All the
propositions that are pre-supposed are called premises, and the one that is claimed to follow from the others is
called the conclusion. Premises are
connected by an implied and, while the premises are all group together, then
the conclusion is connected to the premises by a conditional.
Typical examples of premise indicators
are: for, since, because, given, given that, whence, assuming that, seeing
that, granted that, this is true because, the reason for, for the reason that,
by the fact that, inasmuch as, etc.
Typical examples of conclusion indicators are: thus, therefore, hence,
so, consequently, accordingly, ergo, thereupon, it follows that, which shows
that, as a result, in conclusion, finally, en fin, etc. Neither of these lists is exhaustive (I am
not a linguist); but, hopefully the lists will assist the student in detecting
the premises and conclusion. The
conclusion typically ends the argument but does not have to. For example the argument (albeit simple),
“Annie goes to the store, if Mickey want milk,” has the conclusion preceding
the premise.
Let us consider another argument:
“If I enroll in the course and study hard, then I will
earn acceptable grades. If I
make satisfactory grades, then I am content. I am not content. Hence, either I
did not enroll in this course or I did not study hard.”
“If I enroll in
the course and study hard, then I will earn acceptable grades” is premise one.
“If I make
satisfactory grades, then I am content” is premise two.
“I am not
content” is premise 3.
“Either I did not
enroll in this course or I did not study hard” is the conclusion.
Note that the
conclusion concludes the argument (duh) and it is typically (but not always)
separated from the premises by the transitional word hence.
Now symbolising the argument, let E
denote “I enroll in the course,” S denote “I study hard,” G denote “I earn
acceptable (satisfactory) grades,” and C denote “I am content.” Thus the
argument is
[(E Ù S ®G) Ù (G ® C) Ù (ØC)] Þ [ØE Ú ØS].
Note by order of
operations, premise one is represented as (E Ù S) ®G (with parentheses which for clarity is quite
helpful). Referring to truth table
1.5.1, note only row 8, row 12, and row 16 result in the conjunction of the
three premises being true. Thus, for row
1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14, and 15 we get a final true for the argument since false implies anything is
true! [6] When one completes the truth table, he will
get for the statement ØE Ú ØS true in rows 8, 12, and 16. Thus, the argument is always true.
An argument, which is always true, is
said to be valid; an argument where
there exists at least one combination of truth-values for the premises and
conclusion such that the argument is false is said to be invalid. Thus, note only tautological arguments are valid; whereas
both arguments that are fallacies and contradictions are invalid.[7]
Truth Table 1.4.1
(incompleat; compleat in exercise 1)
E (1) |
S (2) |
G (3) |
C (4) |
E Ù S (5) |
E Ù S ® G (6) |
G ® C (7) |
ØC (8) |
6 Ù 7 Ù 8 (9) |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
F |
T |
T |
T |
T |
Perhaps one of the simplest and most
useful argument forms is modus ponens. Consider the premises p ® q; p; thus, q.
This is a simple argument consisting of two premises; namely, if p, then
q and p. It has a conclusion, q. Let us
let p be “you understand logic” and q be “you pass the test” (you can put any
simple sentence in for p and any other simple sentence in for q). So, the argument is: If you understand logic,
then you will pass the test. You
understand logic. Thus, you pass the
test.
Truth Table 1.4.2
P |
Q |
P ® Q |
(P ® Q) Ù P |
(P ® Q) Ù P Þ Q |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
T |
F |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
T |
F |
T |
F |
F |
T |
F |
T |
Thus, in the
construction of arguments we may use this as a valid argument form for
justification of an argument.
Fundamental primitive true[8]
statements in a system are called axioms.
Such statements are agreed upon to be true.
Further statements derived from the axioms are called lemmas, theorems,
or corollaries. A theorem is a further statement proven from the axioms. If the theorem is of a “sufficiently” small
scale and is used to prove a larger claim, then it is called a lemma (consider it a ‘helper’ theorem).
If a theorem follows so clearly and obviously from another theorem, then it is
called a corollary.
A proof
or mathematical argument is an argument such that it consists of a finite sequence
of statements, each of which is either a premise, an axiom, or a previously
proven lemmas, theorems, or corollaries, or follows from the premises, axioms,
or previously proven theorems by
application of correct modes of inference (logic). The last statement is the conclusion that
follows from the given set of premises.
A proof is announced by writing Proof before the argument and is closed
by writing QED (which means quod erat
demonstratum[9]
loosely translated means, ‘so it has been demonstrated’) at the end. The application of the correct modes of
inference is the “map” of the proof and the proof and QED the frame to announce
to a reader where the proof begins and where it ends. Furthermore, the claim being proven should be
succinctly stated (otherwise oft one will be left with a very confused
audience).
A proof is to be clear, hopefully
concise, and correct. A proof is not to
be some sort of magic trick where slight of hand, misdirection, etc. are
employed. A proof should understandable
(assuming the reader has the requisite background). A magician pulls a rabbit out of a hat
because of a concealed compartment, a gambler win a hand of poker because of an
ace up his sleeve, a businessman gets a contract because of “connections.” None
of these are reasonable concepts for the mathematician. The mathematician objectively seeks the
truth. The mathematician justifies his
inferences. The mathematician explains
his work. And the way the mathematician
does these things is by constructing sound proofs or counter-arguments.
You may assume any of the laws of logic
from section 1.3. Those are premises
that are not stated. Therefore, even in
the most simple of claims there are many premises besides the stated ones; but
they are agreed true statements that are being assumed. Note we do not assume that the fallacy of
assuming the conclusion, etc. may be used.
That which is assumed must be an axiom, previously proven theorem, a
stated premise, or a law of logic.
Let us look at an example of a claim and
a proof of the veracity of the claim.
Example 1.4.1
Claim: If I am spent, then I shall rest. I am not resting.
Therefore, I am not spent.
Let S denote “I
am spent,” and R denote “I rest.” Thus,
the claim is
S ® R. ØR. \ ØS.
Proof:
1. S ® R 1.
Premise.
2. ØR 2.
Premise.
3. ØR ® ØS 3.
Contrapositive form of line 1.
4. ØS 4.
Modus Ponens (line 2 and line 3).
QED
Note that the proof was done in a “vertical” form such that each
statement is justified. Further note the
claim was really an application of modus tollens (and was valid by modus
tollens). This should demonstrate that
there is no one mode of reasoning that is right. There are many but they must be
correct (not fallacious). In
mathematics, an elegant proof is considered one which is the shortest most
compleat argument such that if one word, one letter (perhaps) were deleted the
proof would tumble and no longer be valid.
It is not the object of this class (or any other that I ever teach) to
instruct a student on elegance. A proof
is valid so long as it contains all that is required. If it is longer that another - - so be
it. Therefore, no one will be encouraged to
attempt elegance; you will be encouraged simply to be right (and that is quite
enough, I guarantee it [quote Justin Wilson]).
Now, let’s consider a more challenging
claim.
Example 1.4.2
Claim: Given the
premises ØA Ù C, B Þ D, and Ø(D Ù ØA). The
conclusion ØB follows.
Proof:
1. ØA Ù C 1.
Premise.
2. ØA 2.
Law of Simplification (line1)
3. Ø(D Ù ØA) 3.
Premise.
4. ØD Ú Ø(ØA) 4.
DeMorgan’s Law (line 3).
5. ØD Ú A 5.
Law of Double Negation (line 4).
6. ØD 6.
Disjunctive Syllogism (lines 2 and 5).
7. B Þ D 7.
Premise.
8. ØB 8.
Modus Tollens (lines 6 and 7).
QED
Let us consider the use of this form of
proof. There are other forms (most often
referred to as horizontal form proofs since they are written more in the style
of everyday Western writing. Let us look at the following claim and compare and
contrast the techniques of writing a proof.
Example 1.4.3
Claim: Given the
premises P Ú Q, ØS, P Þ ØR, and R Ú S. The
conclusion Q follows.
Proof (1): Consider R Ú S. Let us assume ØS. So, R.
Assume P Þ ØR. So, ØP. Assume P Ú Q. Thus,
Q. QED.
Proof (2): Consider R Ú S (it can be assumed since it is a premise). Let us
assume ØS since it too is a premise. So, R must follow by the disjunctive
syllogism. Assume P Þ ØR since it is a premise. So, ØP must follow by modus tollens. Assume P Ú Q since it is a premise. Thus, Q follows by the disjunctive
syllogism. Hence, the conclusion follows
from the premises. QED.
Proof (3):
1. R Ú S 1.
Premise.
2. ØS 2.
Premise.
3. R 3.
Disjunctive Syllogism (1,2).
4. P Þ ØR 4.
Premise.
5. Ø(ØR) 5.
Law of Double Negation (3).
6. ØP 6.
Modus Tollens (4, 5).
7. P Ú Q 7.
Premise.
8. Q 8.
Disjunctive Syllogism (6, 7).
QED
Note that proof (1) is correct. However, the deletion of the justification
leaves the reader to recall the reasons why the statements follow. Note proof (2) is correct, but with the added
loquacious manner, it is not the best technique to follow when one is trying to
establish a comfort with method of proof.
Hence, proof (3) is the most satiating since it combines parsimony with
detail. So, for now we will follow technique (3). In time (Math 255), the student will begin to
use proof technique (2); and, eventually, he will be comfortable enough to use
technique (1) [with regard to logic - - the particular justification in a
mathematical area will oft be required by professors so that clarity is
maintained].
One might reasonably ask must every proof
begin with the premises and end with the conclusion. The answer is, “no.” So far we have consider claims such that it
is facile to assume the premises and derive the conclusion. However, we must keep in mind that not all
claims are true (so we will be discussing the methods of disproof - -
counterexample) and even if a claim is true, it may not be so easy to prove in
a direct manner such as we have seen to this point.
The straight-forward method employed so far is:
Direct Proof (1): To prove the conclusion C from a set of premises {say
P1, P2, P3,
. . ., Pk} show that C is provable as a consequent of the set
of premises (hypotheses) P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk.
The practical
meaning is:
I want to prove
ASSUMING the premises P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk that C follows from them; so,
I assume P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk are true and prove that C follows from these premises.
Nonetheless, suppose the conclusion is an
implication. In this case we may employ a different method of proof that is
still direct.
Direct Proof (2): To prove the implication A Þ B from a set of premises {say P1, P2,
P3, . . ., Pk} it
is sufficient to include A in the set of premises {e.g.: A, P1, P2,
P3, . . ., Pk} and
show that B is provable as a consequent of the augmented set of premises
(hypotheses).
The practical
meaning is:
I want to prove
ASSUMING the premises P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk that A Þ B follows
from them,
so, it is equivalent to: Assume
A, P1, P2, P3,
. . ., Pk are
the premises and prove that (B) follows from these. This can be done since the law of logic
assume the hypothesis of the conclusion,
(P Þ (R Þ Q)) Þ (P Ù R) Þ Q, is true.
Let us consider a claim that can be proven using the direct proof (2)
method (it does not have to be proven
in this manner, it is just convenient to do so).
Example 1.4.4
Claim: Given the
premises A Þ B, C Þ D, (B Ù D) Þ ØE, and E it is the case that
A Þ ØC follows as a conclusion.
Proof :
1. A 1.
Hypothesis of the conclusion.
2. A Þ B 2.
Premise.
3. B 3.
Modus Ponens (1,2).
4. E 4.
Premise.
5. (B Ù D) Þ ØE 5.
Premise.
6. Ø(B Ù D) 6.
Modus Tollens (4, 5).
7. ØB Ú ØD 7.
DeMorgan’s Law (6).
8. ØD 8.
Disjunctive Syllogism (3, 7).
9. C Þ D 9.
Premise.
10. ØC 10.
Modus Tollens (8, 9).
QED
Nonetheless, claims are not true every
time they are posed. Thus, a need to
discuss proper techniques for demonstrating that a claim is false is also a
matter that must be discussed. A
counter-argument that demonstrates a claim is false is known as a counterexample. It is constructed in a similar, but not
identical, manner as a proof. Recall
that the form of a proof is 1) the announcement of the proof by writing,
“proof,” followed by the argument, followed by the announcement that is is
done, “QED.” Similarly, the form for a
counterexample begins with a declaration that a counterexample is being
proposed; thus, announced by writing, “counterexample,” then the counterexample
is declared which is an assignment of truth values for all the prime
statements, then the writer demonstrates that it is indeed a counterexample by
noting the argument is false with the assigned truth values, and, finally the
counterexample is declared finished by writing “EEF,” which means exemplum est factum[10]
loosely translated means, ‘the example is fact) at the end.
Consider the following claim: Given the
premises A Þ B, C Þ D, (B Ù D) Þ ØE, and E it is the case that ØC follows as a conclusion. Note that it is similar to the previous claim
(which does not mean that it is false necessarily – more than one conclusion
may be derived from a given set of premises (see the exercise set at the end of
this section). Nonetheless, this is a false claim. One can discern the lack of veracity by doing
a compleat truth table (which is a fine method, but then one need to present
the truth table in the compleat counterexample form, thus exhausting much
time). One can discern that it is false by considering that argument forms
follow the strict pattern of an inferred “and” between each premise, and an
inferred conditional connecting the premises to the conclusion, for what we are
saying is that if the premises are
true, does it the conclusion logically follow? Note, that it does not matter
how silly the hypotheses are- it is the argument that we are considering
and the implication of premises to conclusion.
Thus, each of the premises must be true and the conclusion false.
Therefore, let ØC be false which necessarily implies that C is true by
the law of the excluded middle. Since C
is true and one of the premises is C Þ D, since the hypothesis of this conditional is true,
the consequent must also be true. So, D
is true. Note that there is a unique E as a premise. It must be true. So, now considering the premise (B Ù D) Þ ØE, we have ØE is false and when the consequent is false the only
way for the implication to be true is if the antecedent is also false. We already have D is true, so the only way to
make this whole premise true is if we assign a false for B. So, B is false. Now, let us turn our attention to the last
premise (which was the first in the list [note: order does not matter, what
matters is getting it right]) A Þ B, we already said B is false which forces A to be
false also to make sure the premise is true. All of the aforementioned analysis
is conducted by a student either in his head (if he has an excellent memory) or
on scratch paper. Now we are ready for
the counterexample.
Example 1.4.5
Claim: Given the
premises A Þ B, C Þ D, (B Ù D) Þ ØE, and E it is the case that ØC follows as a conclusion.
Counterexample :
Let A be false, B
be false, C be true, D be true, and E be true.
Consider the
claim [ (A Þ B) Ù (C Þ D) Ù (B Ù D) Þ ØE) Ù (E) ] Þ ØC
Which is [ (F Þ F) Ù (T Þ T) Ù (F Ù T) Þ ØT) Ù (T) ] Þ ØT
So, [ ( T
) Ù ( T ) Ù ( F Þ F ) Ù (T) ] Þ F
Thus, [ ( T
) Ù ( T ) Ù ( T ) Ù (T) ] Þ F
Hence, So, T Þ F
Which is false.
EEF.
Note the first line is the counterexample
(in actuality that is it). However,
demonstrating that it is indeed a counterexample does two things: first, it
helps the student realise he is right (or wrong and must propose a different
counterexample); and, second, it helps the reader follow the logic of the
counterexample (especially when there is a complex claim).
Now, let us consider another claim:
Claim: Given the
premises A Þ ØB, ØA Þ ØC, C, D Þ B, it is the case that ØD follows as a conclusion.
Suppose the conclusion seems to follow
from the premises, but it is not easily seen directly. In this case we may
employ a different method of proof called indirect.
Indirect Proof (1):
For the above
claim let us use reducto ad absurdum (loosely
translated mans, reduce to the absurd), also
called proof by contradiction.[11]
To prove Q follows from a set of premises {say P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk }it is sufficient to
consider ØQ as an additional premise {say ØQ, P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk } and prove a statement of the form ØR Ù R, where R is any statement following from the
premises and the negation of the conclusion. The practical
meaning of this is that when one wants to prove ASSUMING the
premises P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk that Q follows from them, it is equivalent to assuming ØQ, P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk are the premises and prove that () follows from
these where
can be any
statement and its negation that follows (which is the contradiction - - because
it is nonsensical to claim that R and not R can be true at the same time
because it is a violation of the law of the excluded middle). With that being the case, then the addition
of not Q to the hypotheses must have been in error! So, since all the hypotheses P1, P2,
P3, . . ., Pk were assumed true and ØQ, P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk is false, then ØQ must
be false as
a consequent to P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk, ergo Q must follow
(since there were only two possibilities, Q and ØQ)!
Moreover, an important principle of proof
must also be noted before attacking the claim.
That is there is another technique we must mention, adjunction. If P is provable from the set of premises {say P1,
P2, P3, . . ., Pk
} and Q is provable from the same set of premises, then P Ù Q is provable from that set of premises. The practical meaning of this is let us
suppose you are doing a proof (any method)
that P is provable from the set of premises (P1, P2,
P3, . . ., Pk),
later you do a
proof Q is provable from the same set of premises logic ‘tells’ us that P Ù Q is a result of P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk. In ordinary circumstances such has already
been deduced, but when doing a proof there are times one needs a statement of
the form P Ù Q and one already has shown P follows from the
premises and Q follows from the premises.
Thus, we use the justification of adjunction to note that we have P Ù Q. It will
become clear in the next proof (note lines 8, 9, and 10).
Let us now return to the claim and a
proof of the veracity of the claim using
reducto ad absurdum:
Example 1.4.6
Claim: Given the
premises A Þ ØB, ØA Þ ØC, C, D Þ B, it is the case that ØD follows as a conclusion.
Proof :
1. Ø(ØD) 1.
Negation of the conclusion.
2. D 2.
Law of Double Negation (1).
3. D Þ B 3.
Premise.
4. B 4.
Modus Ponens (2, 3).
5. A Þ ØB 5.
Premise.
6. ØA 6.
Modus Tollens (4, 5).
7. ØA Þ ØC 7.
Premise.
8. ØC 8.
Modus Ponens (6, 7).
9. C 9.
Premise
10. ØC Ù C 10.
Adjunction (8, 9).
11. ØD 11.
Contradiction (1, 10).
QED
Normally, many
mathematicians skip the illustration of the law of double negation. I have included it in this example for the
sake of clarity.
I cannot underrate the importance of this
method of proof. Oft times I have found
myself with nary a hope of proving a claim, but then when I attacked the claim
indirectly, it became facile. Further,
there are some claims that cannot be proven directly (that I know of); for
example, it is the case considering the real numbers that is irrational.[12] Given the nature of the irrationals (the name
alone conjures up an image of something that is not very ‘nice’) one can see
that properties of the rationals are such that they are ‘nice,’ so assuming
is rational will lead us to a contradiction (we will prove
this to be the case in Set Theory or Advanced Calculus I).
Let us consider another important
principle of proof. There is another
technique we must mention, substitution.[13] Suppose you have a set of premises (say P1,
P2, P3, . . ., Pk
) and hold Pa (one
of the premises) is obtainable from another say, Pb, by substituting a statement R for any occurrence of a
statement S in Pa. Then we can
derive Pb from
S Û R and
Pa. The
practical meaning
of this is when you have a set of premises
(say P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk ) and you want to show a
particular one of the premises is derivable from another one of the premises
the equivalence statement S Û R means S can replace any occurrence of R or visa
versa by substituting in any part of the proof. In ordinary circumstances such
has already been deduced or given (the equivalence of some statement S and R
e.g.: D º ØØD
by the law of double negation), but when doing a proof there are times one
needs a statement of the form R and one already has shown S follows from the
premises. Thus, we use the justification
of substitution to note that we have R.
It will become clear in the next proof (note lines 8, 9, and 10).
Example 1.4.7
Claim: Given the
premises A Ú B, ØA , C Þ E, C Û B, it is the case that E follows as a conclusion.
Proof :
1. ØA 1.
Premise.
2. A Ú B 2.
Premise.
3. B 3.
Disjunctive Syllogism (1, 2).
4. C Þ E 4.
Premise.
5. C Û B 5.
Premise.
6. C 6.
Substitution (3, 5)
7. E 7.
Modus Ponens (6, 4).
QED
Oft times substitution comes in some
interesting forms; for example, in reduction of fractions in arithmetic,
polynomial expressions in algebra, etc. You will find it a useful technique; but be
careful for it is only allowable such that there is a logical equivalence, not
in a simple implication form. For
example because C Û B, we could substitute C for B, but if we had C Þ B we could not.
Some of the ‘trickiest’ cases with the erroneous use of substitution
occurs in real analysis. Consider the
real numbers and the function f (x) =
x + 1 where f (x) goes from the reals
to the reals. Note it is a line. Is g(x)
= the same? Can we
substitute g (x) for f (x)?
The answer is, “no.” Note (from
your understanding of functions from high school) that f (1) exists, but g (1)
does not. Therefore, the two could not
be the same (we will explore this in more depth throughout your mathematical
studies). Suffice it to say that some
things look deceptively true when
indeed they are false.
Also, let us note that in the preceding
discussion we had premises that were consistent. A set of premises is consistent if
contradiction does not follow from them.
A set of premises is inconsistent
if a contradiction (a statement of the form R Ù ØR) necessarily follows from them.
Note, therefore,
we use the inconsistency of adjoining the negation of the conclusion to a given
set of premises to arrive at a contradiction when we use the technique of reducto ad absurdum.
Some times a given set of premises is incompleat, which is to say if there
was just one or more conditions added to the list of premises, then we could
prove a particular conclusion.
Researchers find this to be the case often (where they have to
strengthen hypotheses).
Consider we
assume A Þ (B Þ C) is true and we wish to deduce ØA. We
cannot! However, if we could argue that
B Ù ØC are true; then we could prove this along with A Þ (B Þ C) forces ØA. Much in
science explicitly or implicitly relates to this type of scenario. However, it is beyond the scope of the
course and lays groundwork which I feel is harmful. This is because oft times students add
hypotheses to problems that are not stated nor implied!
For example, consider the problem of solving = 0 for the real numbers.
Note (from your understanding of functions from high school) that
= 0 Þ x =
Ú x = -
. Many students would
say the answer does not exist (they are thinking only of rational numbers)
which is wrong. Many students would write the solution as
thinking that means x
=
Ù x = -
which is wrong. Many students
would write x = 2.2360679775 or
x = -
2.2360679775 (which are approximations on a calculator) which is wrong. Consider the
claim that many high school students allow: for the real numbers
which is false (suppose
x = 0). Indeed consider one of my favourites: Reduce
completely . Many students claim
this is equal to x - y; it is not
(solve it yourself).
I could drone on, but suffice it to say that some things look deceptively right when indeed they are wrong. So incumbent on you, the student,
is the responsibility to learn how to properly, correctly, and precisely reason
and to ‘toss off’ the shackles of answers gained by external methods
(calculators), added hypotheses which are not correct, etc.
Let us direct our attention to a given
set of premises and let us deduce a conclusion that follows form the given set
of premises. For example, consider ØA Þ ØB, B, A Þ C what necessarily follows from these premises? Since B is given note by modus tollens that A
follows. However, that is not very satiating since we have not used all the
premises (but it is not wrong since
there is no method of proof that states all premises must be used; if
all the premises are not used, then the premises not used are called unnecessary premises or superfluous premises and in research would be discarded before a final
presentation [if the researcher realised that it was not used]). Since B is
given note by modus tollens that A follows and that since A ÞC is given it therefore follows that C is a conclusion
that follows. Note that ØC could not follow!
However, Ø(ØC) follows as does Ø(Ø(Ø(ØC))), etc. So, may logically equivalent statements
follow from a given set of premises.
Could it be the case that two different conclusions can follow? The answer is, “yes,” when we allow for
unnecessary premises.
Consider the premises to be K Þ L, M Þ N, O Þ N, P Þ L, ØN Ú ØL, ØM Ú ØO. Note that ØN Ú ØL º N Þ ØL; thus, since M Þ N is a premise it follows we have M Þ ØL. But, M Þ ØL º L Þ ØM; thus, since P Þ L is a premise we can derive P Þ ØM by the hypothetical syllogism. However, note since we have ØN Ú ØL º ØL Ú ØN º L Þ ØN; thus, since K Þ L is a premise, we get K Þ ØN. But, M Þ N is a premise, so M Þ N º ØN Þ ØM; thus, K Þ ØM. On the other hand, ØM Ú ØO º ØO Ú ØM º O Þ ØM which leads nowhere.
So, there are different conclusions that can be drawn from the
premises. One might say the best was a
conclusion that uses the most premises; and one should always seek such
conclusions. I am not in that
school. What I advocate (profess) is
that it is important for a student of mathematics to be right, to know why he
is right (therefore, he justifies himself), and to communicate that to others
(communicate - - not condescend). The
last comment is, perhaps, the most important for it is not the case that we
wish to ‘keep the secrets’ of mathematics to ourselves, but to share our
understanding with others. However, it
is not the case that this profession is predicated on the principle of doing it
for others. A professor of mine (now
deceased) at Georgia State used to have on his office door the saying (I am
paraphrasing) that, “to give a man a fish means he will eat for a day; but, to
teach a man to fish means he will be able to eat for a lifetime.” Therefore, reading this text is not enough,
you must do for yourself; hence, the exercise set follows.
§ 1.4 EXERCISES.
1. Given the
premises A Þ (B Ú C), B Þ ØC; prove or disprove that A Þ B follows as a conclusion.
2. Given the
premises A Þ B, A Ú C Þ D; prove or disprove that B Þ D follows as a conclusion.
3. Given the
premises A Þ B, C Þ D, (B Ú D) Þ E, E; prove or
disprove that A ÞØ C follows as a
conclusion.
4. Given the
premises S Þ P, D Ú (Q Ù S), ØD; prove or disprove that P follows as a conclusion.
5. Given the
premises A Þ M, Ø(M Ù ØS), ØS Ù B; prove or disprove that ØA follows as a conclusion.
6. Given
the premises D Ù ØN Ú S, S Þ ØJ; prove or disprove that J Þ D follows as a conclusion.
7. Given the
premises D Ú S Þ A, D Ú A; prove or disprove that A follows as a conclusion.
8. Given the
premises D Ú (S Þ A), D Ú A; prove or disprove that A follows as a conclusion.
9. Given the
premises (D Ú S) Þ A, D Ú A; prove or disprove that A follows as a conclusion.
10. Given the
premises S Þ P, P Þ (W Ú J), ØW Ù S; prove or disprove that J follows as a conclusion.
11. Given the
premises A Þ U, ØU Ú (B Ù ØJ), ØA Þ ØB, Ø(ØJ Ù ØA) Ú B; prove or disprove that J Þ ØA follows as a conclusion.
12. Given the
premises A Þ U, ØU Ú (B Ù ØJ), ØA Þ ØB, Ø(ØJ Ù ØA) Ú B; prove or disprove that J Þ A follows as a conclusion.
13. Given the
premises A Þ U, ØU Ú (B Ù ØJ), ØA Þ ØB, Ø(ØJ Ù ØA) Ú B; prove or disprove that ØA Þ J follows as a conclusion.
14. Given the
premises P Þ Q, R Ú ØQ, Ø(ØP Ú ØS); prove or disprove that R Ù S follows as a conclusion.
15. Given the
premises ØP Þ (Q Þ R), R Ù S Þ T, U Þ (Q Ù S), Ø(ØU Ú P); prove or disprove that T follows as a conclusion.
16. For the given
set of premises, determine a suitable conclusion such that the argument
is valid:
A. Premises: p ® q , r ® Øq
B. Premises: p ® Øq , q
C. Premises:
p ® Øq , r ®p , q
17. Given the
following “proof,” detect the error(s) in the “proof” and explain why it is
(are) an error(s). Please be brief,
but write legibly and in compleat sentences!
Justification for each step will not be provided since it is not a
proof.
Claim: Given the premises
ØB Ú C, ØA Þ B; the conclusion C Ù ØA follows.
“Proof:”
1. ØA 6. C Ù ØA
2. ØA Þ B “QED”
3. B
4. ØB Ú C
5. C
§ 1.5 MORE ON
LOGIC PROOFS.
There are more proof techniques that we
need to add to our ‘bag of tricks.’ One
of these is the method of proof by cases. Cases is not like what we have
discussed previously because the techniques of direct and indirect proof are
truly different; whereas, proof by cases is a method that is subsumed under the
other type of methods. It is most useful
in both algebra and analysis, so spend some time concentrating on the
technique, when it is useful, and how to do it.[14]
Proof by cases: To prove P Ú Q Þ R it is
necessary & sufficient to prove R follows from P and R follows from
Q. The practical meaning of this is you do a proof (direct or indirect) that R follows logically from P, then later
you do a proof (any method) R follows
logically from Q , then logically P Ú Q Þ R. Note that
This can be generalised to P1 Ú P2 Ú P3 Ú . . .
Ú Pk Þ R such
that k is a natural number. As the number of cases increases, one generally
pauses and considers trying a method other than cases; but, cases no matter if
there are 2 or 1,000,000 will work if it works (a wonderfully obvious comment
on my part).
Example 1.5.1
Claim: Given the premises
A Ú B, B Þ ØC; prove or disprove the conclusion A Ú ØC follows.
Proof :
1. B Þ ØC 1.
Premise.
2. A Ú B 2.
Premise.
Case 1: 3a. A
3a. Cases Case
2: 3b. B 3b.
Cases
4a. A Ú ØC 4a. Law of Addition (3a) 4b. ØC 4b. Modus
Ponens (3b, 1)
5b. ØC Ú A 5b. Law of Add (4b)
6b. A Ú ØC 6b.
Commutative (5b).
Hence, A Ú ØC.
QED
Note that in each case the conclusion
must follow. Note that when executing
case 2, nothing from case 1 can be referenced (so in the example above only
lines 1 or 2 can be referenced in case 2; not lines 3a or 3b). Hopefully, you can see the example was a
bit stilted for there was an easier way to prove the claim; but, it suffices to
illustrate that each case is done separately.
Now let us turn our attention to yet
another method of proof that we may employ.
It is different than previous methods, but is still direct.
Direct Proof (3) (by contraposition): To prove the
implication A Þ B from a set of premises (say P1, P2,
P3, . . ., Pk ) it
is sufficient to include ØB in the set of premises (e.g.: ØB, P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk) and show that ØA is provable as a consequent of the augmented set of
premises (hypotheses). Notice this is
using the contrapositive form of the conclusion. We are not assuming the negation of the
conclusion (which would be Ø(A Þ B)) which is an indirect form of proof this
contraposition form is direct. The
practical meaning is suppose you want to
prove ASSUMING the premises P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk that A Þ B follows from them, so, it is equivalent to: assume ØB, P1, P2, P3, . . ., Pk are the premises and prove that ØA follows from these. I do not have acquaintance with
many people who use this technique often; but, it is a valid method. Further, it seems to me to be most useful
when there are negations in the conclusion.
For example, consider:
Example 1.5.2
Claim: Given the premises
A Ú B, ØB, A Þ C, D Ù C Þ E; prove or disprove the conclusion ØE Þ ØD follows.
Proof:
1. Ø(ØD) 1.
Negation of consequent of conclusion
2. D 2.
Law of Double Negation (1).
3. ØB 3.
Premise
4. A Ú B 4. Premise.
5. A 5.
Disjunctive Syllogism (3, 4).
6. A Þ C 6.
Premise
7. C 7.
Modus Ponens (5, 6).
8. D Ù C 8.
Adjunction (2, 7)
9. D Ù C Þ E 9.
Premise
10. E 10.
Modus Ponens (8, 9).
11. Ø(ØE) 11.
Law of Double Negation.
QED
Finally, let us consider not really
another proof technique so much as a particular type of conclusion which when
claimed to conclude from a given set of premises, how we can ‘best’ write up an
understandable and correct proof.
Proof for a biconditional: To prove the biconditional A Û B from a set of premises (say P1, P2,
P3, . . ., Pk ) it
is sufficient to prove A Þ B as a consequent of the premises and to prove B Þ A as a consequent of the premises. Notice this is in fact doing two proofs
(reminiscent of cases, but rather than cases we are using the fact that A Û B º (A Þ B Ù B Þ A).
Consider:
Example 1.5.3
Claim: Given the premises C Þ A, ØC Þ ØJ, A Þ M, ØM Ú J; it is the case that J Û A follows.
Proof:
(Þ) 1. J 1.
Hypothesis of the conclusion in the (Þ) direction[15].
2. ØC Þ ØJ 2.
Premise
3. J Þ C 3.
Contrapositive (2) [and law of double negation]
4. C Þ A 4.
Premise
5. J Þ A 5.
Hypothetical Syllogism (3, 4)
6. A 6.
Modus Ponens (1, 5).
(Ü) 1. ØJ 1.
Negation of the consequent in the (Ü) direction[16].
2. ØM Ú J 2.
Premise
3. ØM 3.
Disjunctive Syllogism (1, 2)
4. A Þ M 4.
Premise
5. ØA 5.
Modus Tollens (3, 4)
QED
Nonetheless, it is sufficient to show
that a biconditional claim is false in one direction when the claim is indeed
false. Consider the claim:
Example 1.5.4
Claim: Given the premises
P Þ Q, R Ú ØQ, Ø(ØP Ú ØS); it is the case that ØR Û S follows as a conclusion.
Counterexample:
Let P be true, Q
be true, R be true, and S be true.
Consider the
claim [ (P Þ Q) Ù (R Ú ØQ) Ù (Ø(ØP Ú ØS))] Þ (S Þ ØR)
Which is [ (T Þ T) Ù (T Ú ØT) Ù (Ø(ØT Ú ØT))] Þ (T Þ ØT)
So, [ ( T
) Ù (T Ú F ) Ù ( T Ù T ) ] Þ (T Þ F)
Thus, [ ( T
) Ù ( T ) Ù ( T ) ] Þ F
Hence, So, T Þ F
Which is false.
Since it is false
in the (Ü) direction, it does not matter what the truth value
of the (Þ) direction is; hence, the claim is false.
EEF.
§ 1.5 EXERCISES.
1. Given the
premises A Þ (B Ú C), B Þ ØC; prove or disprove that A Û B follows as a conclusion.
2. Given the
premises (P Ù ØQ) Ú (Q Ù ØR), P Þ S, ØS Ú T, ØT; prove or disprove that Q follows as a conclusion.
3. Given the
premises P Ú ØQ, P Ú Q; prove or disprove that P follows as a conclusion.
4. Given the
premises P Ú ØQ, P Ú (Q ® R); prove or disprove that P follows as a conclusion.
5. Given the
premises P Ú R, Q ® R, ØR; prove or disprove that ØP follows as a conclusion.
6. Given the
premises X ® A, P ® X, A ® M, ØM Ú P; prove or disprove that A Û P follows as a conclusion.
7. Given the
premises X ® P, P ® (W Ú Z), ØW Ù X; prove or disprove that Z follows as a conclusion.
8. Given the
premises ØE ® G, Ø(B Ù E); prove or disprove that B Þ G follows as a conclusion.
9. Translate the
following arguments into symbols and prove or disprove the claim:
A. If Bob doesn’t
win, then Kenneth will not win. Sean
will win, if Kenneth does not win. Sean didn’t win. Therefore, Bob won.
C. If Winston or Halbert wins then Luke and
Susan cry. Susan does not cry. Thus, Halbert does not win.
D. If I enroll in the course and study hard,
then I will earn acceptable grades. If I make satisfactory grades, then I am
content. I am not content. Hence, either
I did not enroll in this course or I did not study hard.
E. If the population increases rapidly and
production remains constant, then prices rise.
If prices rise then the government will control prices. I am rich then I do not care about increases
in prices. It is not true that I am not
rich. Either the government does not control prices or I do not care about
increases in prices. Therefore, it is not the case that the population
increases rapidly and production remains constant.
F. Dean praises me only if I can be proud of
myself. Either I do well in classes or I
cannot be proud of myself. If I do my
best in sports, then I cannot be proud of myself. Therefore, if Dean praises me, then I do my
best in sports.
G. It was murder or suicide. There was no weapon
found at the scene of the crime and if it was murder, there would be a
motive. If there was a motive, then
there would be a weapon at the scene of the crime. Thus, it was suicide.
H. If he is elected, then he will go to Atlanta
or Washington. It is not the case that
he will run for office and go to Washington. He will run for office and be
elected. Therefore, he will go to
Atlanta.
I. If he is a Democrat or a Republican, he shall
run for office. If he is not a Democrat,
then he will run for office. Therefore,
he will run for office.
J. If he is not cautious, then it is false that
he is tempestuous and contemplative. He
is contemplative and he is tempestuous or strong. He isn’t strong. Therefore, he is cautious.
§ 1.6 MORE ON
FALLACIES.
There exist at least three functions or uses of language according to
philosophy:
1) the
informative function - in which language is used to inform;
2) the expressive
function - in which language is used to express feelings, emotions, or
attitudes of the actor or to evoke feelings, emotions, or attitudes to the
listener or reader: and,
3) the directive
function - in which language is used to cause or prevent certain overt or
covert actions.
Only in case 1 of the above can we, perhaps, determine the veracity of a
statement; indeed, there are many instances where the veracity may not be
determinable. An example of a statement the veracity of which can be determined
is, “It is the year 2002 A.D..” An
example of a statement the veracity of which cannot be determined is, “Julius
Caesar said, ‘goodbye,’ to Livia before leaving for the Senate on the ides of
March 44 B.C..”
We have defined the three possible truth
values of a statement (or argument) to be tautology, fallacy, and
contradiction. Further, we noted there
are different types of fallacies, such as the fallacy of the assertion of the
conclusion of a conditional, the fallacy of denial of the hypothesis of a conditional, the fallacy
of the inverse of a conditional, and the fallacy of the converse of a
conditional.
There are other types of fallacies which though may be emotionally,
politically, psychologically, etc. persuasive are nonetheless fallacies because
the are examples of incorrect reasoning. These are typically referred to as
common or everyday fallacies of idiomatic English or fallacies of rhetoric.
Rhetoric or elocution, a way with words, the “gift of gab,” advocacy, etc. are
possibly fine traits and assist a person in everyday life but they have no
place in mathematical reasoning.
The fallacy of Petitio Prencipii, or
begging the question, is an example.
The fallacy of relevance is such that the
premises are logically irrelevant to the conclusion. Its premises are not relevant to the
objective of establishing the truth of the conclusion. One may easily see this if one notes the
power of emotive language that through clever use of language a person may
persuade an audience to accept a particular conclusion even though a logically
correct argument was not used to show the particular conclusion must follow
from a set of premises.
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Bacculum, or the appeal to force, is such that one
uses the threat of force or coercion to cause acceptance of a particular
statement. One cannot prove that
Catholicism is true by arguing that you will be damned if you don’t agree that
Catholicism is true!
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Hominem takes on many form.
The fallacy of Argumentum ad
Hominem (1), or the abusive, is such that one tries to cause rejection of a
proposition by attacking, insulting, criticising, disparaging, or abusing a
person who asserts a proposition rather that presenting evidence to disprove
the truth of a particular proposition. Oft used to cause anger, resentment,
etc. in the audience so that said hostility
clings to the person proposing a statement and transfers to the proposition
itself. It is perhaps sound advise to note that one’s attitude toward the
person proposing a statement should be held independent of the actual statement
since it is independent of the
statement.
The fallacy of Argumentum ad
Hominem (2), or the circumstantial (1), is such that two or more people
disagree about the truth of some proposition and when one or more (the actors),
instead of trying to prove the truth of the assertion, tries to cause
acceptance of the assertion on the grounds that if follows from the other’s
(adversary) beliefs. Just because it follows from one’s beliefs does not
establish the veracity of a proposition for the beliefs themselves may be
erroneous. The fallacy of Argumentum ad
Hominem (2) is a valid form of debate for an actor to note an inconsistency
in an adversary’s position; but, to conclude that the author’s position is
correct is false since both positions might be in error.
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Hominem (3), or the circumstantial (2), is such that
a person concludes that a particular position is false on the grounds that the
opponent asserts the proposition because of special circumstance and not for an
objective reason. Showing self-interest
in the opponent rather than objective evidence as to why the opponent’s
position is wrong does not prove the proposition false. Once again, this
fallacy may be an effective debating technique, but does nothing to establish
whether a proposition is true or false.
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Ignorantiam, or the argument from ignorance, is such
that one argues a position based on false information, faulty information, lack
of information, or one’s imagination; further one concludes a proposition is
false since it has not been proved true or one concludes a proposition is true
since it has not been proved false.
This position is most easily represented by the position of “it is my
opinion [even though there is no evidence to support such] . . .” as if one has
a right to be wrong. It can also be
represented by, “the N. I. H. found no evidence to suggest that holistic
medicine is harmful. Thus, holistic
medicine is good for you.” Perhaps my favourite example of argumentum ad
ignorantiam is “statistics proves [fill in the blank].”[17]
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Misericordiam, or the argument from misery or pity,
is such that one ‘argues’ a position based on pity (the speaker emotes the
audience to feel pity for him or his position, thus getting the audience to
acquiesce to his conclusion).
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Populum, or the argument from the popular, is such
that one argues a position based on emotive advertising, propoganda, or appeal
to the “majority.” There are two types most often refernced in this fallacy:
the appeal to snobbery (example: the Polo crest) or the “band-wagon” effect
(example: everyone is doing it...).
The fallacy of Argumentum ad Verecundiam, or the appeal to authority, is such that
one argues a position based on an appeal to an authority that is in fact not an
authority on the particular subject. For
example, consider that Dr. Pepper recommends flossing one’s teeth. That Dr. Pepper recommends flossing in no way
establishes that flossing is an idea which should be accepted. Dr. Pepper is a
soda not a dentist; but, there are many examples of the abuse of the term
“doctor.”
The fallacy of Accident is such that one argues a generalisation or heuristic is
usually true, so therefore in a particular case it is true whereas it does not
hold in the particular case. For example, consider that a claim that most
students take 16 semestre hours each semestre does not imply that Mr. Y is
taking sixteen hours.
The fallacy of Converse Accident, or a hasty generalisation, is such that one argues that a property holds for an individual
case or class of cases, therefore it holds in general. This is the fallacy of
inductive reasoning since there is no guarantee that there is any reason for
generalisation.[18]
The fallacy of False Cause is such that one argues a particular causal effect from
a given set of premises and a causal connection to a conclusion, which in fact
erroneously connects the premises and conclusion. The most common example is
when a researcher does not understand statistics and logic and notes that X
preceded Y, there is a connection between the two (often a property called
linear correlation), and thus X caused Y.
The fallacy of Complex Question occurs when a complex question is posed such that
a yes or no answer is given, but there remains a part (not posed) of the
complex question assumed a priori
answered which was not answered. There
are many types of complex questions, but a type which stands out is one where much
previous is inferred. For example, ”Are
you in favour of pulling out of Afghanistan and letting Al Qaeda and the
Taliban rape the country again?”
The fallacy of Ignoratio Elenchi, or irrelevant conclusion, is one where a person
argues a given set of premises support a particular conclusion but the premises
force a different conclusion. However, the argument may be so emotionally or
psychologically appealing as to render the audience willing to agree that the
proposed conclusion follows from the premises.
The fallacy of Ambiguity is a fallacious argument form relying on an ambiguous
word or phrase which causes the argument to be fallacious with the shift in
meaning of the word or phrase. There are at least five ways the fallacy of
ambiguity can be committed: through equivocation, amphibole, accent,
composition, or division. An example would be all beds are made. All maids are
skirted. Thus, all beds are skirted. In
writing it is clearly fallacious, but in sound it could be misunderstood.
Reviewing this short list of fallacies
helps us to understand that rhetoric as opposed to proper logic is fraught with
problems. It is not the job of the
mathematician to convince, influence, persuade, etc. An
argument properly constructed should do it (suffice).[19]
[1] We will drop the quotation marks when it is understood that we are referencing a symbol rather that a letter. Often this is difficult to do; for example, suppose one wants to use the variable “a” and they wish to reference a particular one of the a’s. It would be a problem to say let us consider a a. Hopefully, this will not occur in this text.
[2] We will rigorous discuss the theory of sets in chapter 2. Suffice it to say, I am assuming that you had some basic introduction to arithmetic and we are not moving beyond the scope of our introduction to logic by discussing these basic sets. When introducing an area of mathematics to a student, it is oft times difficult because each student enters the course with some prior introduction to the area (whether it be a correct introduction or an incorrect introduction; more on this comment later).
[3] This will be made clear in Math 255, Set Theory.
[4] This is obvious, but let’s take a closer look. Note P Ú ØP is logically equivalent to ØP Ú P which by the or form into implication form is P Þ P !!!! Now, if anyone (usually in the Humanities or Social Sciences) says the Law of the Excluded Middle is an antiquated, outdated, or invalid law ask them, “ ‘If - - - -, then - - - -‘ [fill in the blank] is a fallacy?”
[5] By the same token note that Ø(P Ú ØP) is logically equivalent to ØP Ù Ø(ØP) which is ØP Ù P which is
P Ù ØP. Since ØP Ú P is always true it must be the case that P Ù ØP is always false.
[6] Recall F Þ T is true as well as F Þ F is true.
[7] A statement is neither valid nor invalid. We are not assigning truth values to statements exclusive of the opposing possibility.
[8] Technically assumed to be true or agreed to be true since they cannot be proven true.
[9] I have also seen it translated as “thus it has been proved.”
[10] I created this to give balance to the process of proving or disproving a claim. Since a proof begins with the word ‘proof’ and ends with QED it is logical to begin a counterexample with ‘counterexample’ and end with EEF.
[11] My favourite method. Note: this does not imply it will be yours or that you should always attempt to prove a claim using this method. I am simply noting it is my favourite method for your edification.
[12] See chapter 2 for a definition of real, irrational, rational, etc. numbers
[13] This method is hard to write out & explain, but I believe you will find it the easiest to do and through the doing will understand it better.
[14] For example, in real analysis we have the trichotomy law which state that any real number x must be either less than zero, equal to zero, or greater than zero and never more than one of these at any time. So, many times one considers a general w (a real) and does three cases (case 1: w < 0; case 2: w = 0; and, case 3: w > 0).
[15] Note this is direct proof (2) technique in the (Þ) direction.
[16] Note this is direct proof (3) technique in the (Ü) direction (so different methods can be employed in each direction).
[17] Since I have a Ph.D. in Statistics, suffice it to say that this bothers me. Statistics do not prove a thing; statistics only demonstrates evidence to suggest something.
[18] This should be distinguished from the valid method of proof called mathematical induction, which DOES prove a general claim.
[19] Note should does not imply would. Whilst it is the case that a properly constructed argument (proof) cannot be denied, it is also the case that humans are full of contradiction, biases, etc. Thus, we shall see that in mathematics as opposed to the “real world” our arguments will stand on their own. Such cannot be said about life in general or in particular.